Skip to main content

On legislating from a Libertarian perspective

Regular readers will note that I have been struggling with Dr. Tal Scriven's Wrongness, Wisdom, and Wilderness, Toward a Libertarian Theory of Ethics and the Environment for about a week now.

It's heavy sledding: Scriven writes in that both lean and obtuse manner of modern philosophers, but the ideas beneath are very intriguing.

Scriven proposes that within the social contract for the creation of governments it is only philosophically ethical for a government to take action to prevent harm rather than to provide benefit.

[We could go around and around on what consitutes harm in this sense, which Scriven freely admits, but let that wait for a second.]

On that basis, he provides a four-point checklist that should be applied to any new law:

However, at this point we may formulate the harm principle in terms of the following conditions, which are individually necessary and jointly sufficient to justify the enforcement of a social proscription:

1. The proscription must be made reasonably clear.

2. The proscription must be capable of universal promulgation within the jurisdiction of the proscription. Morever, it must be reasonably well promulgated within that jurisdiction.

3. The type of action (or inaction) proscribed must be shown to pose a serious danger of harm.

4. The harm associated with the type of action (or inaction) proscribed must not be outweighed by the pleasures associated with that type of action (or inaction) and the harms associated with proscribing it.


Again, the burden of proving that all of these conditions obtain is on the
state, not the individual....

It should be obvious that this principle poses a test that is far more demanding than those routinely suggested by legislators' arguments even in fairly libertarian countries like the United States.


Maybe it all should be obvious, but let me try to re-state his four requirements for a law to be ethically justified under a libertarian philosophy in something approximating plain English:

1. The law must be clearly and unambiguously written.

2. The law must be universally publicized.

3. The law must prohibit an action (or an inaction) that can be demonstrated to pose serious harm to individuals.

4. The law may not be enacted if either (a) the pleasure (or good) associated with the action/inaction outweighs the harm; or (b) if prohibiting such actions/inactions creates a greater harm than leaving it alone.


Two further clarifications:

1. Scriven defines harm pretty narrowly:

Harm should include not only physical pain but also death and severe psychological suffering.


2. Action/inaction. As Scriven describes it, the definition of action would be pretty simple: bludgeoning someone to death with a hammer is an action causing harm [whether the need to cause that harm could later be justified or not].

Inaction comes from the Bad Samaritan principle, which holds that people should be held accountable for their failure to provide an easy rescue. The example Scriven uses is this: you are sitting in a chair within arm's length of a pool wherein a small child is drowning. You could easily reach out and pull the child to safety at no risk or even great inconvenience. If you do not, you have by inaction allowed harm to occur. [This is obviously a much stickier situation for many libertarians, who see potential for extensive State intervention over the definition of easy rescue, but Scriven would argue that it's still not ethical or acceptable in a Libertarian society to allow that child to drown.

While not agreeing with everything that Scriven writes, I find him to be an intriguing thinker, and I believe he is pointing the way to serious principles and discussions that the modern libertarian movement--however constituted--should be considering.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Comment Rescue (?) and child-related gun violence in Delaware

In my post about the idiotic over-reaction to a New Jersey 10-year-old posing with his new squirrel rifle , Dana Garrett left me this response: One waits, apparently in vain, for you to post the annual rates of children who either shoot themselves or someone else with a gun. But then you Libertarians are notoriously ambivalent to and silent about data and facts and would rather talk abstract principles and fear monger (like the government will confiscate your guns). It doesn't require any degree of subtlety to see why you are data and fact adverse. The facts indicate we have a crisis with gun violence and accidents in the USA, and Libertarians offer nothing credible to address it. Lives, even the lives of children, get sacrificed to the fetishism of liberty. That's intellectual cowardice. OK, Dana, let's talk facts. According to the Children's Defense Fund , which is itself only querying the CDCP data base, fewer than 10 children/teens were killed per year in Delaw

With apologies to Hube: dopey WNJ comments of the week

(Well, Hube, at least I'm pulling out Facebook comments and not poaching on your preserve in the Letters.) You will all remember the case this week of the photo of the young man posing with the .22LR squirrel rifle that his Dad got him for his birthday with resulted in Family Services and the local police attempting to search his house.  The story itself is a travesty since neither the father nor the boy had done anything remotely illegal (and check out the picture for how careful the son is being not to have his finger inside the trigger guard when the photo was taken). But the incident is chiefly important for revealing in the Comments Section--within Delaware--the fact that many backers of "common sense gun laws" really do have the elimination of 2nd Amendment rights and eventual outright confiscation of all privately held firearms as their objective: Let's run that by again: Elliot Jacobson says, This instance is not a case of a father bonding with h

The Obligatory Libertarian Tax Day Post

The most disturbing factoid that I learned on Tax Day was that the average American must now spend a full twenty-four hours filling out tax forms. That's three work days. Or, think of it this way: if you had to put in two hours per night after dinner to finish your taxes, that's two weeks (with Sundays off). I saw a talking head economics professor on some Philly TV channel pontificating about how Americans procrastinate. He was laughing. The IRS guy they interviewed actually said, "Tick, tick, tick." You have to wonder if Governor Ruth Ann Minner and her cohorts put in twenty-four hours pondering whether or not to give Kraft Foods $708,000 of our State taxes while demanding that school districts return $8-10 million each?